[TYPES] What's a program? (Seriously)

Jason Gross jasongross9 at gmail.com
Wed May 19 08:03:05 EDT 2021


Non-truncated Excluded Middle (that is, the version that returns an
informative disjunction) cannot have a computational interpretation in
Turing machines, for it would allow you to decide the halting problem.
More generally, some computational complexity theory is done with reference
to oracles for known-undecidable problems.  Additionally, I'd be suspicious
of a computational interpretation of the consistency of ZFC or PA ----
would having a computational interpretation of these mean having a type
theory that believes that there are ground terms of type False in the
presence of a contradiction in ZFC?

On Wed, May 19, 2021, 07:38 Talia Ringer <tringer at cs.washington.edu> wrote:

> [ The Types Forum, http://lists.seas.upenn.edu/mailman/listinfo/types-list
> ]
>
> Somewhat of a complementary question, and proof to the world that I'm up at
> 330 AM still thinking about this:
>
> Are there interesting or commonly used logical axioms that we know for sure
> cannot have computational interpretations?
>
> On Wed, May 19, 2021, 3:24 AM Neel Krishnaswami <
> neelakantan.krishnaswami at gmail.com> wrote:
>
> > [ The Types Forum,
> http://lists.seas.upenn.edu/mailman/listinfo/types-list
> > ]
> >
> > Dear Sandro,
> >
> > Yes, you're right -- I didn't answer the question, since I was too
> > taken by the subject line. :)
> >
> > Anyway, I do think that HoTT with a non-reducible univalence axiom is
> > still a programming language, because we can give a computational
> > interpretation to that language: for example, you could follow the
> > strategy of Angiuli, Harper and Wilson's POPL 2017 paper,
> > *Computational Higher-Dimensional Type Theory*.
> >
> > Another, simpler example comes from Martin Escardo's example upthread
> > of basic Martin-Löf type theory with the function extensionality
> > axiom. You can give a very simple realizability interpretation to the
> > equality type and extensionality axiom, which lets every compiled
> > program compute.
> >
> > What you lose in both of these cases is not the ability to give a
> > computational model to the language, but rather the ability to
> > identify normal forms and to use an oriented version of the equational
> > theory of the language as the evaluation mechanism.
> >
> > This is not an overly shocking phenomenon: it occurs even in much
> > simpler languages than dependent type theories. For example, once you
> > add the reference type `ref a` to ML, it is no longer the case that
> > the language has normal forms, because the ref type does not have
> > introduction and elimination rules with beta- and eta- rules.
> >
> > Another way of thinking about this is that often, we *aren't sure*
> > what the equational theory of our language is or should be. This is
> > because we often derive a language by thinking about a particular
> > semantic model, and don't have a clear idea of which equations are
> > properly part of the theory of the language, and which ones are
> > accidental features of the concrete model.
> >
> > For example, in the case of name generation – i.e., ref unit – our
> > intuitions for which equations hold come from the concrete model of
> > nominal sets. But we don't know which of those equations should hold
> > in all models of name generation, and which are "coincidental" to
> > nominal sets.
> >
> > Another, more practical, example comes from the theory of state. We
> > all have the picture of memory as a big array which is updated by
> > assembly instructions a la the state monad. But this model incorrectly
> > models the behaviour of memory on modern multicore systems. So a
> > proper theory of state for this case should have fewer equations
> > than what the folk model of state validates.
> >
> >
> > Best,
> > Neel
> >
> > On 19/05/2021 09:03, Sandro Stucki wrote:
> > > Talia: thanks for a thought-provoking question, and thanks everyone
> else
> > > for all the interesting answers so far!
> > >
> > > Neel: I love your explanation and all your examples!
> > >
> > > But you didn't really answer Talia's question, did you? I'd be curious
> > > to know where and how HoTT without a computation rule for univalence
> > > would fit into your classification. It would certainly be a language,
> > > and by your definition it has models (e.g. cubical ones) which, if I
> > > understand correctly, can be turned into an abstract machine (either a
> > > rewriting system per your point 4 or whatever the Agda backends compile
> > > to). So according to your definition of programming language (point 3),
> > > this version of HoTT would be a programming language simply because
> > > there is, in principle, an abstract machine model for it? Is that what
> > > you had in mind?
> > >
> > > Cheers
> > > /Sandro
> > >
> > >
> > > On Wed, May 19, 2021 at 6:21 AM Neel Krishnaswami
> > > <neelakantan.krishnaswami at gmail.com
> > > <mailto:neelakantan.krishnaswami at gmail.com>> wrote:
> > >
> > >     [ The Types Forum,
> > >     http://lists.seas.upenn.edu/mailman/listinfo/types-list
> > >     <http://lists.seas.upenn.edu/mailman/listinfo/types-list> ]
> > >
> > >     Dear Talia,
> > >
> > >     Here's an imprecise but useful way of organising these ideas that I
> > >     found helpful.
> > >
> > >     1. A *language* is a (generalised) algebraic theory. Basically,
> think
> > >          of a theory as a set of generators and relations in the style
> of
> > >          abstract algebra.
> > >
> > >          You need to beef this up to handle variables (e.g., see the
> > work of
> > >          Fiore and Hamana) but (a) I promised to be imprecise, and (b)
> > the
> > >          core intuition that a language is a set of generators for
> terms,
> > >          plus a set of equations these terms satisfy is already totally
> > >          visible in the basic case.
> > >
> > >          For example:
> > >
> > >          a) the simply-typed lambda calculus
> > >          b) regular expressions
> > >          c) relational algebra
> > >
> > >     2. A *model* of a a language is literally just any old mathematical
> > >          structure which supports the generators of the language and
> > >          respects the equations.
> > >
> > >          For example:
> > >
> > >          a) you can model the typed lambda calculus using sets
> > >             for types and mathematical functions for terms,
> > >          b) you can model regular expressions as denoting particular
> > >             languages (ie, sets of strings)
> > >          c) you can model relational algebra expressions as sets of
> > >             tuples
> > >
> > >     2. A *model of computation* or *machine model* is basically a
> > >          description of an abstract machine that we think can be
> > implemented
> > >          with physical hardware, at least in principle. So these are
> > things
> > >          like finite state machines, Turing machines, Petri nets,
> > pushdown
> > >          automata, register machines, circuits, and so on. Basically,
> > think
> > >          of models of computation as the things you study in a
> > computability
> > >          class.
> > >
> > >          The Church-Turing thesis bounds which abstract machines we
> > think it
> > >          is possible to physically implement.
> > >
> > >     3. A language is a *programming language* when you can give at
> least
> > >          one model of the language using some machine model.
> > >
> > >          For example:
> > >
> > >          a) the types of the lambda calculus can be viewed as partial
> > >             equivalence relations over Gödel codes for some universal
> > turing
> > >             machine, and the terms of a type can be assigned to
> > equivalence
> > >             classes of the corresponding PER.
> > >
> > >          b) Regular expressions can be interpreted into finite state
> > >     machines
> > >             quotiented by bisimulation.
> > >
> > >          c) A set in relational algebra can be realised as equivalence
> > >             classes of B-trees, and relational algebra expressions as
> > nested
> > >             for-loops over them.
> > >
> > >         Note that in all three cases we have to quotient the machine
> > model
> > >         by a suitable equivalence relation to preserve the equations of
> > the
> > >         language's theory.
> > >
> > >         This quotient is *very* important, and is the source of a lot
> of
> > >         confusion. It hides the equivalences the language theory wants
> to
> > >         deny, but that is not always what the programmer wants – e.g.,
> is
> > >         merge sort equal to bubble sort? As mathematical functions,
> they
> > >         surely are, but if you consider them as operations running on
> an
> > >         actual computer, then we will have strong preferences!
> > >
> > >     4. A common source of confusion arises from the fact that if you
> have
> > >          a nice type-theoretic language (like the STLC), then:
> > >
> > >          a) the term model of this theory will be the initial model in
> > the
> > >             category of models, and
> > >          b) you can turn the terms into a machine
> > >             model by orienting some of the equations the lambda-theory
> > >             satisfies and using them as rewrites.
> > >
> > >          As a result we abuse language to talk about the theory of the
> > >          simply-typed calculus as "being" a programming language. This
> is
> > >          also where operational semantics comes from, at least for
> purely
> > >          functional languages.
> > >
> > >     Best,
> > >     Neel
> > >
> > >     On 18/05/2021 20:42, Talia Ringer wrote:
> > >      > [ The Types Forum,
> > >     http://lists.seas.upenn.edu/mailman/listinfo/types-list
> > >     <http://lists.seas.upenn.edu/mailman/listinfo/types-list> ]
> > >      >
> > >      > Hi friends,
> > >      >
> > >      > I have a strange discussion I'd like to start. Recently I was
> > >     debating with
> > >      > someone whether Curry-Howard extends to arbitrary logical
> > >     systems---whether
> > >      > all proofs are programs in some sense. I argued yes, he argued
> > >     no. But
> > >      > after a while of arguing, we realized that we had different
> > >     axioms if you
> > >      > will modeling what a "program" is. Is any term that can be typed
> > >     a program?
> > >      > I assumed yes, he assumed no.
> > >      >
> > >      > So then I took to Twitter, and I asked the following questions
> > (some
> > >      > informal language here, since audience was Twitter):
> > >      >
> > >      > 1. If you're working in a language in which not all terms
> compute
> > >     (say,
> > >      > HoTT without a computational interpretation of univalence, so
> not
> > >     cubical),
> > >      > would you still call terms that mostly compute but rely on
> axioms
> > >      > "programs"?
> > >      >
> > >      > 2. If you answered no, would you call a term that does fully
> > >     compute in the
> > >      > same language a "program"?
> > >      >
> > >      > People actually really disagreed here; there was nothing
> > resembling
> > >      > consensus. Is a term a program if it calls out to an oracle?
> > >     Relies on an
> > >      > unrealizable axiom? Relies on an axiom that is realizable, but
> > >     not yet
> > >      > realized, like univalence before cubical existed? (I suppose
> some
> > >     reliance
> > >      > on axioms at some point is necessary, which makes this even
> > >     weirder to
> > >      > me---what makes univalence different to people who do not view
> > >     terms that
> > >      > invoke it as an axiom as programs?)
> > >      >
> > >      > Anyways, it just feels strange to get to the last three weeks of
> > my
> > >      > programming languages PhD, and realize I've never once asked
> what
> > >     makes a
> > >      > term a program 😅. So it'd be interesting to hear your thoughts.
> > >      >
> > >      > Talia
> > >      >
> > >
> >
>


More information about the Types-list mailing list